Skip to main content

Introduction to Philosophy: Teaching Method, Course Description, Lesson Samples.

Description of Courses Taught

Jennifer Lawson

University of North Florida (2006-09)

Introduction to Phil

Overview

Philosophy deals with the deepest questions the human species has asked. In my classes, I carefully navigated my students through issues such as the existence of God, artificial intelligence, epistemology, metaphysics, ethics, and logic. I used standard materials.

I began the course with a cursory prep on informal logic. I graded students’ essays on the ability to avoid informal fallacies. Therefore, I didn’t necessarily care what they argued as long as the logic was good.

I used a modified version of the Socratic Method. I actually led discussion and directed it, but encouraged class discussion where students didn’t attack each other but attacked me. I often began my lesson by going over things on the chalkboard. Then I would lead discussion. It was important to me that my students knew how to navigate the issues rather than learning from rote, being perplexed, or anything else.

I kept office hours and encouraged students to come to me with questions, look over papers, and general guidance about philosophy, college, and careers. I believed I trained philosophers, rather than people who just took an Intro class.

I tried to be entertaining. But this was college. My students were there for serious business. I gave them my best every time—even if I felt exhausted at the end of the day.

I began the course each time by telling my students we were equals. I really meant this. We were dealing with issues together because I don’t know everything. This also helped me avoid discrimination in any form because I took all of my students to be equal partners in our education.

I used Blackboard. I posted grades very soon so my students could know how they were doing.


__________________



Below is the outline of a lecture on John Stuart Mill’s ethics, from his book Utilitarianism, delivered in a lecture hall to over 100 students at the University of North Florida.

Mill Lecture Sample from Introduction to Philosophy

By Jennifer Lawson

Introduction

Mill begins his discussion by talking about ‘intuitive’ moral theories. By this he means moral theories that propose to come to solutions to moral problems a priori rather than inductively or empirically. Recall, a priori means ‘by reason alone’. Rarely do thinkers in the intuitive school make a list of a priori principles, according to Mill. Kant, however, does. His a priori principle is the categorical imperative: “Act according to the maxim you could will to be a universal law.”

When we look at the categorical imperative, though, what we see is that Kant does not show that immoral acts are actually logical contradictions. What he does show is that, if we look at the consequences of an immoral action, the consequences are such that no one would want them. So, Kant’s theory actually deals with consequences and whether consequences are favorable or not, according to Mill.

Greatest Happiness Principle

The Greatest Happiness Principle (or, the Principle of Utility) is that actions are right insofar as they promote happiness and wrong insofar as they promote the reverse of happiness.

What is happiness? Pleasure. What is the reverse of happiness? Pain.

Higher and Lower Pleasures

Utilitarian theory had been accused of being a ‘swine theory’. That is, people found it insulting that all humans should do is maximize pleasures. This is because they took pleasure to be mere bodily pleasure.

Mill, however, says we need to distinguish between higher and lower pleasures. Higher pleasures are pleasures of the mind: Reading literature, going to the opera. Lower pleasures are bodily pleasures. Human beings value both and higher pleasures have more value than lower pleasures.

When we are faced with two pleasures, Mill says that the way we determine which pleasure is of greater value is this: For any person competently acquainted with both pleasures, the one s/he chooses as the more pleasurable is the more valuable one.

No human would choose to be an animal and no educated person would choose to be a dunce. Why? Because humans have dignity. “Better to be a human unsatisfied than a pig satisfied.”

Rejection of Virtue Theory

Mill rejects virtue theory. That is, he doesn’t think character traits of motivations are incredibly valuable the way a virtue theorist might. What is important, again, is the consequences of actions and whether those consequences produce happiness, or pleasure.

Mill says that some people think utilitarianism makes people cold and unfeeling, that it doesn’t take into account important traits of human beings. Mill replies that utilitarianism is about right action. Assessing virtues is about judging people. Furthermore, there is nothing incompatible with valuing good persons in utilitarianism. And, good people can do bad things, while bad people can do good things.

Act and Rule Utilitarianism

Bentham advocated act utilitarianism. Act utilitarianism is the position that we should tally the consequences of each act we perform. Mill, on the other hand, advocate rule utilitarianism. Rule utilitarianism is the position that many social rules we have came about because of what we have learned about pleasure and pain in the past. We already know that stealing creates pain. Our society prohibits stealing. This is a rule for us: Don’t steal. An act of stealing would be immoral because it breaks a rule which we’ve already decided on.

We should consult the principle of utility only when faced with dilemmas.

______________________


SAMPLE INFORMAL LOGIC LESSON FROM INTRODUCTION TO PHILOSOPHY

By Jennifer Lawson

Claims

When you are confronted with an argument, the first thing you want to do is figure out what kind of claims are being made. This way, you will know how to assess the claims.

A claim can be:

Empirical: The truth or falsity can be assessed by looking into the world.

Example: “All crows are black.”

It would be hard to examine every crow in the world, but if you really want to assess this claim to see if it’s true, you’d look into the world.

A Priori: The truth or falsity cannot be assessed by looking into the world. Usually these claims are said to be assessed by mere reason: thinking about it, examining the concepts.

Example: “A bachelor is an unmarried male.”

Normative: Normative claims are prescriptive. They purport to say what ought to be.

Example: “You should never kill another human.”

Here are some further examples:

My arm is bleeding. (Empirical)

A triangle is a three sided figure. (A priori)

Shouldn’t you make better use of your time? (Normative)

There cannot be a square circle. (A priori)

Smoking increases your risk for heart disease. (Empirical)

Thou shall not covet thy neighbor’s wife. (Normative)

Logic

We make a distinction between inductive and deductive arguments.

An inductive argument is one which, if the premises are true, the conclusion is only probable.

Example:

Every time I have gone to my mom’s house and knocked on the door, her dog, Flip, ran to the door and barked. I am about to knock on my mom’s door. Therefore, Flip will bark.

This is only probable because (A) Flip could have died. (B) Flip could be in the back yard. (C) Flip may have been trained to not bark when someone knocks at the door. Or any number of other reasons. Still, it is probable that Flip will bark next time I knock.

A deductive argument is one which, if the premises are true, the conclusion must be true.

Example:

Socrates is a man

All men are mortal

Therefore, Socrates is mortal

If the premises are true, then the conclusion that Socrates is mortal is necessarily true.

Deductive arguments can be called valid and sound.

When an argument is vaild, that means it’s in a good form. Validity describes a good logical form.

When an argument is sound, that means its form is good and it has true premises.

Here are some examples of vaild argument forms:

Modus Ponens

p→q

p

therefore, q Modus Tollens

p→q

not q

therefore, not p Hypothetical Syllogism

p→q

q→r

therefore, p→r Disjunct

p or q

p

therefore, not q

If the statements put inside these variables are true, the conclusion must be true.

For example, let’s look at Modus Ponens:

If one is a dog, one goes to heaven.

Spot is a dog.

Therefore, Spot goes to heaven.

This is an example of Modus Ponens. This argument is valid. And, if the premises were true, it would also be sound.



Comments

Popular posts from this blog

A Hanukkah Message on Furher Trump From One Yet Living

President-Elect (notice how I've never disputed that he won the 2024 election) Donald Trump has been frothing at the mouth in Hitlerian fashion , threatening to claim Canada, Greenland, and the Panama Canal.  Perhaps he knows--perhaps he doesn't--that these are war threats he is making. He seems pretty damn confident that The Department of Defense will do as he says, as if he were already--or is going to be--an absolute ruler.  Not to belabor this point, but my direct ancestral lineage, from which we get our current military, fought The American Revolutionary War so we wouldn't have an absolute ruler. Far worse than a king, Donald J. Trump is aiming to be a dictator along the lines of Vladimir Putin, who has attacked Ukraine, which The United States, along with allies, have been supporting since Day 1.  Caught in his frothy dreams, to Trump, the world may look like his oyster. He must know our military's fame; he must be confident of it. With due respect to the presiden...

Free Readings! & Readings Available For Purchase! (2024)

M y Writing Year In Review (2024). I graduated with my M.A. in 2023. Despite having sepsis, pneumonia, bronchitis, and being diagnosed with Stage 1 cancer in 2024, I managed to be more prolific this year than most years.  Below is my year in review, separated by what you can read for free, and the few things available for purchase. Here's what you can read for free: I started the year by writing a book review that was oh-so-controversial .  The next day or so, I proceeded to write the paper " Radical Logic ," which I first submitted to The United States Military. It is now declassified and open to everyone. I was then offered a chance to write about my true passion. I decided to write about a problem I had been working on for years: infinite cardinal numbers .  I made two arguments on transgender language. I defended them publicly and then made a  finale argument, which basically tells TERFS that they don't understand the English language . Here's what you can pay...

Sgt. Marion Lester Lawson (Special Forces, Korean Conflict)

My dad was in the the military during the Korean Conflict. Today, he would be known as a Green Beret . Below is a coffee cup I thought I had lost that he bought for me me when I was 8 years old. I infrequently get manic and give away stuff that I actually love. You can visit my dad's memorial online  here . Veteran's Affairs has thoughtfully put his grave online, which is nice because I don't have to go all the way to Texas to put a daisy wreath on his grave. I've put some weird stuff on it, but I've also put some really great stories on it.  Everyone who knew him has different stories to tell--some good, some bad. Above is a picture of my dad and my daughter on the day he cooked buffalo burgers and grilled corn on the cobb that he grew himself. When I was older, my dad had the bracelet below engraved for me. I thought I had lost that, too.  It says "Jennifer" on one side, and "Dad" on the other. My dad's song for me was "The Yellow Rose...